PHILOSOPHICAL THEORIES OF KNOWLEDGE: ESPITEMOLOGY OF EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM
EPISTEMOLGY
The term “epistemology” comes from the
Greek “episteme,” meaning “knowledge,” and “logos,” meaning, roughly, “study,
or sience, of.” “Logos” is the root of all terms ending in “-ology” – such as
psychology, anthropology – and of “logic,” and has many other related meanings.
Epistemology,
in a most general way, is that branch of philosophy which is concerned with the
value of human knowledge. It describes, analyses, examines genetically the
facts of knowledge as such (psychology of knowledge), and then tests chiefly
the value of knowledge and of its various kinds, its conditions of validity,
range and limits (critique of knowledge).
Epistemology
attempts to answer the basic question: what distinguishes true (adequate)
knowledge from false (inadequate) knowledge? It also forms one of the pillars
of the new sciences cognition, which developed from the information processing
approach to psychology, and from artificial intelligence, as an attempt to
develop computer programs that mimic a human’s capacity to use knowledge in an
intelligent way.
Epistemologists
concern themselves with a number of tasks, which we might sort into two
categories.
First,
we must determine the nature of knowledge; that is, what does it mean to say that
someone knows, or fails to know, something? This is a matter of understanding
what knowledge is, and how to distinguish between cases in which someone knows
something and cases in which someone does not know something. While there is
some general agreement about some aspects of this issue, we shall see that this
question is much more difficult than one might imagine.
Second,
we must determine the extent of human knowledge; that is, how much do we, or
can we, know? How can we use our reason, our senses, the testimony of others,
and other resources to acquire knowledge? Are there limits to what we can know?
For instance, are some things unknowable? Is it possible that we do not know
nearly as much as we think we do? Should we have a legitimate worry about
skepticism, the view that we do not or cannot know anything at all?
HISTORY
OF EPISTEMOLOGY
When we look at the history of epistemology, we can discern a clear
trend, in spite of the confusion of many seemingly contradictory positions. The
first theories of knowledge stressed its absolute, permanent character, whereas
the later theories put the emphasis on its relativity or situation-dependence,
its continuous development or evolution, and its active interference with the
world and its subjects and objects. The whole trend moves from a static,
passive view of knowledge towards a more and more adaptive and active one.
The first efforts of Greek thinkers centre around the study of nature.
This early philosophy is almost exclusively objective, and supposes, without
examining it, the validity of knowledge. Doubt arose later chiefly from the
disagreement of philosophers in determining the primordial elements of matter
and in discussing the nature and attributes of reality. Parmenides holds that
it is unchangeable; Heraclitus, that it is constantly changing; Democritus
endows it with an eternal inherent motion, while Anaxagoras requires an
independent and intelligent motor. This led the Sophists to question the
possibility of certitude, and prepared the way for their skeptical tendencies.
With Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, who oppose the Sophists, the power of the
mind to know truth and reach certitude is vindicated, and the conditions for
the validity of knowledge are examined. But epistemological questions are not
yet treated on their own merits, nor kept sufficiently distinct from purely
logical and metaphysical inquiries. The philosophy of the Stoics is primarily
practical, knowledge being looked upon as a means of right living and as a
condition of happiness. As man must act according to guiding principles and
rational convictions, human action supposes the possibility of knowledge.
THEORIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY
This field also addresses questions about how we construct concepts in
our minds, the nature of knowledge itself, the relationship between what we
"know" and the objects of our knowledge, the reliability of our
senses, and more.
In general, theories about the
relationship between the knowledge in our minds and the objects of our
knowledge can be divided into two types of positions: dualistic and monistic:
Epistemological Dualism: According to this position, the object "out
there" and the idea "in the mind" are two entirely different
things. One might have some similarity to the other, but we shouldn't
necessarily count on it. Critical Realism is a form of Epistemological Dualism because
it subscribes to the view that there is both a mental world and an objective,
outside world. Knowledge about the outside world may not always be possible and
may often be imperfect, but nevertheless it can, in principle, be acquired and
it is essentially different from the mental world of our minds.
Epistemological Monism:
This is the idea that the "real objects" out there and the knowledge
of those objects stand in close relationship with each other. Ultimately, they
are not two entirely different things as in Epistemological Dualism - either
the mental object is equated with the known object, as in Realism, or the known
object is equated with the mental object, as in Idealism. A consequence of this
is that statements about physical objects only make sense if they can be
construed as really being statements about our sense data. Why? Because we are
permanently cut off from the physical world and all we really have access to is
our mental world - and for some, this entails denying that there is even an
independent physical world in the first place.
Epistemological Pluralism: This is a idea which has been made popular in
postmodernist writings and argues that knowledge is highly contextualized by
historical, cultural and other outside factors. Thus, rather than there being
simply one type of thing as in monism (either essentially mental or essentially
physical) or two types of things as in dualism (both mental and physical),
there exists a multiplicity of things which affect the acquisition of knowledge:
our mental and sensory events, the physical objects, and the various influences
upon us which lie outside of our immediate control. This position is also
sometimes referred to as Epistemological Relativism because knowledge is
construed as relative to different historical and cultural forces.
WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?
The first problem encountered in epistemology is that of defining
knowledge. Philosophers use the tripartite theory of knowledge, which analyses
knowledge as justified true belief, as a working model much of the time. The
tripartite theory has, however, been refuted; Gettier cases show that some
justified true beliefs do not constitute knowledge. Rival analyses of knowledge
have been proposed, but there is as yet no consensus on what knowledge is. This
fundamental question of epistemology remains unsolved.
Though philosophers are unable to provide a generally accepted analysis
of knowledge, we all understand roughly what we are talking about when we use
words such as “knowledge”. Thankfully, this means that it is possible to get on
with epistemology, leaving unsolved the fundamental question as to what
knowledge is.
From where do we get our knowledge?
A second important issue in epistemology concerns the ultimate source of
our knowledge. There are two traditions: empiricism, which holds that our
knowledge is primarily based in experience, and rationalism, which holds that
our knowledge is primarily based in reason. Although the modern scientific
worldview borrows heavily from empiricism, there are reasons for thinking that
a synthesis of the two traditions is more plausible than either of them
individually.
How are our beliefs justified?
There are better and worse ways to form beliefs. In general terms, it is
important to consider evidence when deciding what to believe, because by doing
so we are more likely to form beliefs that are true. Precisely how this should
work, when we are justified in belief something and when we are not, is another
topic in the theory of knowledge. The three most prominent theories of
epistemic justification are foundationalism, coherentism, and reliabilism.
How do we perceive the world around us?
Much of our knowledge, it seems, does come to us through our senses,
through perception. Perception, though, is a complex process. The way that we
experience the world may be determined in part by the world, but it is also
determined in part by us. We do not passively receive information through our
senses; arguably, we contribute just as much to our experiences as do the
objects that they are experiences of. How we are to understand the process of perception, and how this should affect our understanding of the world
that we inhabit, is therefore vital for epistemology.
Do we know anything at all?
The area of epistemology that has captured most imaginations is
philosophical skepticism. Alongside the questions of what knowledge is and how
we come to acquire it is the question whether we do in fact know anything at
all. There is a long philosophical tradition that says that we do not, and the
arguments in support of this position, though resisted by most, are remarkably
difficult to refute. The most persistent problem in the theory of knowledge is
not what knowledge is or what it comes from, but whether there is any such
thing at all.
KINDS OF KNOWLEDGE
The
word “knowledge” and its cognates are used in a variety of ways. One common use
of the word “know” is as an expression of psychological conviction. For
instance, we might hear someone say, “I just knew it wouldn’t rain, but then it
did.” While this may an appropriate usage, philosophers tend to use the word
“know” in a factive
sense, so that one cannot know something that is not the case. (This point is
discussed at greater length in section 2b below.)
Even
if we restrict ourselves to factive usages, there are still multiple senses of
“knowledge,” and so we need to distinguish between them. One kind of knowledge
is procedural knowledge, sometimes called competence or “know-how;” for
example, one can know how to ride a bicycle, or one can know how to drive from
Washington, D.C. to New York. Another kind of knowledge is acquaintance
knowledge or familiarity; for instance, one can know the department
chairperson, or one can know Philadelphia.
Epistemologists
typically do not focus on procedural or acquaintance knowledge, however,
instead preferring to focus on propositional knowledge. A proposition is something which
can be expressed by a declarative sentence, and which purports to describe a
fact or a state of affairs, such as “Dogs are mammals,” “2+2=7,” “It is wrong to murder
innocent people for fun.” (Note that a proposition may be true or false; that
is, it need not actually
express a fact.) Propositional knowledge, then, can be called knowledge-that;
statements of propositional knowledge (or the lack thereof) are properly
expressed using “that”-clauses, such as “He knows that Houston is in Texas,” or
“She does not know that the square root of 81 is 9.” In what follows, we will
be concerned only with propositional knowledge.
Propositional
knowledge, obviously, encompasses knowledge about a wide range of matters:
scientific knowledge, geographical knowledge, mathematical knowledge,
self-knowledge, and knowledge about any field of study whatever. Any truth
might, in principle, be knowable, although there might be unknowable truths.
One goal of epistemology is to determine the criteria for knowledge so that we
can know what can or cannot be known, in other words, the know study of
epistemology fundamentally includes the study of meta-epistemology (what we can
about knowledge itself).
We
can also distinguish between different types of propositional knowledge, based
on the source of that knowledge. Non-empirical or a prior knowledge is possible
independently of, or prior to, any experience, and requires only the use of
reason; examples include knowledge of logical truths such as the law of
non-contradiction, as well as knowledge of abstract claims (such as ethical
claims or claims about various conceptual matters). Empirical or a posteriori
knowledge is possible only subsequent, or posterior, to certain sense
experiences (in addition to the use of reason); examples include knowledge of
the color or shape of a physical object or knowledge of geographical locations.
(Some philosophers, called rationalists, believe that all knowledge is
ultimately grounded upon reason; others, called empiricists, believe that all
knowledge is ultimately grounded upon experience.) A thorough epistemology
should, of course, address all kinds of knowledge, although there might be
different standards for a priori and a posteriori knowledge.
THE NATURE KNOWLEDGE
We
must ask ourselves what, exactly, constitutes knowledge. What does it mean for
someone to know something? What is the difference between someone who knows
something and someone else who does not know it, or between something one knows
and something one does not know? Since the scope of knowledge is so broad, we
need a general characterization of knowledge, one which is applicable to any
kind of proposition whatsoever. Epistemologists have usually undertaken this
task by seeking a correct and complete analysis of the concept of knowledge, in
other words a set of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions
which determine whether someone knows something.
Let us begin with the observation
that knowledge is a mental state; that is, knowledge exists in one’s mind, and
unthinking things cannot know anything. Further, knowledge is a specific kind
of mental state. While “that”-clauses can also be used to describe desires and
intentions, these cannot constitute knowledge. Rather, knowledge is a kind of belief.
If one has no beliefs about a particular matter, one cannot have knowledge
about it.
For
instance, suppose that I desire that I be given a raise in salary, and that I
intend to do whatever I can to earn one. Suppose further that I am doubtful as
to whether I will indeed be given a raise, due to the intricacies of the
university’s budget and such. Given that I do not believe that I will be given
a raise, I cannot be said to know that I will. Only if I am inclined to believe
something can I come to know it. Similarly, thoughts that an individual has
never entertained are not among his beliefs, and thus cannot be included in his
body of knowledge.
Some
beliefs, those which the individual is actively entertaining, are called
occurrent beliefs. The majority of an individual’s beliefs are non-occurrent;
these are beliefs that the individual has in the background but is not
entertaining at a particular time. Correspondingly, most of our knowledge is
non-occurrent, or background, knowledge; only a small amount of one’s knowledge
is ever actively on one’s mind.
2) Truth
Knowledge,
then, requires belief. Of course, not all beliefs constitute knowledge. Belief
is necessary but not sufficient for knowledge. We are all sometimes mistaken in
what we believe; in other words, while some of our beliefs are true, others are
false. As we try to acquire knowledge, then, we are trying to increase our
stock of true
beliefs (while simultaneously minimizing our false beliefs).
We
might say that the most typical purpose of beliefs is to describe or capture
the way things actually are; that is, when one forms a belief, one is seeking a
match between one’s mind and the world. (We sometimes, of course, form beliefs
for other reasons – to create a positive attitude, to deceive ourselves, and so
forth – but when we seek knowledge, we are trying to get things right.) And,
alas, we sometimes fail to achieve such a match; some of our beliefs do not
describe the way things actually are.
Note
that we are assuming here that there is such a thing as objective truth, so
that it is possible for beliefs to match or to fail to match with reality. That
is, in order for someone to know something, there must be something one knows about.
Recall that we are discussing knowledge in the factive sense; if there are no
facts of the matter, then there’s nothing to know (or to fail to know). This
assumption is not universally accepted – in particular, it is not shared by
some proponents of relativism – but it will not be defended here. However, we
can say that truth is a condition of knowledge; that is, if a belief is not true, it
cannot constitute knowledge. Accordingly, if there is no such thing as truth,
then there can be no knowledge. Even if there is such a thing as truth, if
there is a domain in which there are no truths, then there can be no knowledge
within that domain. (For example, if beauty is in the eye of the beholder, then
a belief that something is beautiful cannot be true or false, and thus cannot
constitute knowledge.)
Knowledge,
then, requires factual belief. However, this does not suffice to capture the
nature of knowledge. Just as knowledge requires successfully achieving the
objective of true belief, it also requires success with regard to the formation
of that belief. In other words, not all true beliefs constitute knowledge; only
true beliefs arrived at in the right way constitute knowledge.
What,
then, is the right way of arriving at beliefs? In addition to truth, what other
properties must a belief have in order to constitute knowledge? We might begin
by noting that sound reasoning and solid evidence seem to be the way to acquire
knowledge. By contrast, a lucky guess cannot constitute knowledge. Similarly,
misinformation and faulty reasoning do not seem like a recipe for knowledge,
even if they happen to lead to a true belief. A belief is said to be justified
if it is obtained in the right way. While justification seems, at first glance,
to be a matter of a belief’s being based on evidence and reasoning rather than
on luck or misinformation, we shall see that there is much disagreement
regarding how to spell out the details.
The
requirement that knowledge involve justification does not necessarily mean that
knowledge requires absolute certainty, however. Humans are fallible beings, and
fallibilism is the view that it is possible to have knowledge even when one’s
true belief might have turned out to be false. Between beliefs which were
necessarily true and those which are true solely by luck lies a spectrum of
beliefs with regard to which we had some defeasible reason to believe that they
would be true. For instance, if I heard the weatherman say that there is a 90%
chance of rain, and as a result I formed the belief that it would rain, then my
true belief that it would rain was not true purely by luck. Even though there
was some chance that my belief might have been false, there was a sufficient
basis for that belief for it to constitute knowledge. This basis is referred to
as the justification for that belief. We can then say that, to constitute
knowledge, a belief must be both true and justified.
Note
that because of luck, a belief can be unjustified yet true; and because of
human fallibility, a belief can be justified yet false. In other words, truth
and justification are two independent conditions of beliefs. The fact that a
belief is true does not tell us whether or not it is justified; that depends on
how the belief was arrived at. So, two people might hold the same true belief,
but for different reasons, so that one of them is justified and the other is
unjustified. Similarly, the fact that a belief is justified does not tell us
whether it’s true or false. Of course, a justified belief will presumably be
more likely to be true than to be false, and justified beliefs will presumably
be more likely or more probable to be true than unjustified beliefs. (As we
will see in section 3 below, the exact nature of the relationship between truth
and justification is contentious.)
THE EXTENT OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE
Given
the above characterization of knowledge, there are many ways that one might
come to know something. Knowledge of empirical facts about the physical world
will necessarily involve perception, in other words, the use of the senses.
Science, with its collection of data and conducting of experiments, is the
paradigm of empirical knowledge. However, much of our more mundane knowledge
comes from the senses, as we look, listen, smell, touch, and taste the various
objects in our environments.
But
all knowledge requires some amount of reasoning. Data collected by scientists
must be analyzed before knowledge is yielded, and we draw inferences based on
what our senses tell us. And knowledge of abstract or non-empirical facts will
exclusively rely upon reasoning. In particular, intuition is often believed to
be a sort of direct access to knowledge of the a priori.
Once
knowledge is obtained, it can be sustained and passed on to others. Memory
allows us to know something that we knew in the past, even, perhaps, if we no
longer remember the original justification. Knowledge can also be transmitted
from one individual to another via testimony; that is, my justification for a
particular belief could amount to the fact that some trusted source has told me
that it is true.
KEY PROPONENTS
PLATO
In Plato's view
knowledge is merely an awareness of absolute, universal Ideas or Forms,
existing independent of any subject trying to apprehend to them.
In
addition, Plato’s Socrates in the early dialogues may plausibly be regarded as
having certain methodological or epistemological convictions, including:
- Definitional knowledge of ethical terms is at least a necessary condition of reliable judging of specific instances of the values they name (Euthyphro 4e-5d, 6e; Laches 189e-190b; Lysis 223b; Greater Hippias 304d-e; Meno 71a-b, 100b; Republic I.354b-c);
- A mere list of examples of some ethical value—even if all are authentic cases of that value—would never provide an adequate analysis of what the value is, nor would it provide an adequate definition of the value term that refers to the value. Proper definitions must state what is common to all examples of the value (Euthyphro 6d-e; Meno 72c-d);
- Those with expert knowledge or wisdom on a given subject do not err in their judgments on that subject (Euthyphro 4e-5a; Euthydemus 279d-280b), go about their business in their area of expertise in a rational and regular way (Gorgias 503e-504b), and can teach and explain their subject (Gorgias 465a, 500e-501b, 514a-b; Laches 185b, 185e, 1889e-190b); Protagoras 319b-c).
ARISTOTLE
Aristotle puts
more emphasis on logical and empirical methods for gathering knowledge, he
still accepts the view that such knowledge is an apprehension of necessary and
universal principles.
IMMANUEL KANT
According to Kant,
knowledge results from the organization of perceptual data on the basis of
inborn cognitive structures, which he calls "categories". Categories
include space, time, objects and causality. This epistemology does accept the
subjectivity of basic concepts, like space and time, and the impossibility to
reach purely objective representations of things-in-themselves. Yet the a
priori categories are still static or given.
His contributions to epistemology aesthetics have had a profound
impact on almost every philosophical movement that followed him. What can we
know?” The answer, if it can be stated simply, is that our knowledge is
constrained to mathematics and the science of the natural, empirical world. It
is impossible, Kant argues, to extend knowledge to the supersensible realm of
speculative metaphysics. The reason that knowledge has these constraints, Kant
argues, is that the mind plays an active role in constituting the features of
experience and limiting the mind’s access only to the empirical realm of space
and time.
THOMAS AQUINAS
Aquinas made an important contribution to
epistemology, recognizing the central part played by sense perception in human
cognition. It is through the senses that we first become acquainted with
existent, material things. St. Thomas held that the relation of dependence of
objects on something which transcends them is disclosed to the observer through
the contemplation of material things. Just as our knowledge depends not on
innate ideas but perceiving the material world, the same material world is
dependent on a productive agent for its existence. Aquinas thought the
proposition 'everything which begins to exist through the agency of an already
existent, extrinsic thing' to be a fact beyond doubt.
GEORGE EDWARD MOORE
In epistemology, Moore is remembered as a stalwart
defender of commonsense realism. Rejecting skepticism on the one hand, and, on
the other, metaphysical theories that would invalidate the commonsense beliefs
of “ordinary people” (non-philosophers), Moore articulated three different
versions of a commonsense-realist epistemology over the course of his career.
Moore’s epistemological interests also motivated much of
his metaphysical work, which to a large extent was focused on the ontology of
cognition. In this regard, Moore was an important voice in the discussion about
sense-data that dominated Anglo-American epistemology in the early twentieth
century.
Two facts make it difficult to separate Moore’s
contributions to metaphysics from his contributions to epistemology. First, his
main contributions to metaphysics were in the ontology of cognition, which is
often treated as a branch of epistemology. Second, his main contributions to
epistemology were motivated by what he called the “commonsense” or “ordinary”
view of the world, and this is properly a metaphysical conception, a worldview
or Weltanschauung.
EDMUND GETTIER
For
some time, the justified true belief (JTB) account was widely agreed to capture
the nature of knowledge. However, in 1963, he published a short but widely
influential article which has shaped much subsequent work in epistemology.
Gettier provided two examples in which someone had a true and justified belief,
but in which we seem to want to deny that the individual has knowledge, because
luck still seems to play a role in his belief having turned out to be true.
Consider
an example. Suppose that the clock on campus (which keeps accurate time and is
well maintained) stopped working at 11:56pm last night, and has yet to be
repaired. On my way to my noon class, exactly twelve hours later, I glance at
the clock and form the belief that the time is 11:56. My belief is true, of
course, since the time is indeed 11:56. And my belief is justified, as I have
no reason to doubt that the clock is working, and I cannot be blamed for basing
beliefs about the time on what the clock says. Nonetheless, it seems evident that
I do not know that the time is 11:56. After all, if I had walked past the clock
a bit earlier or a bit later, I would have ended up with a false belief rather
than a true one.
This
example and others like it, while perhaps somewhat far-fetched, seem to show
that it is possible for justified true belief to fail to constitute knowledge.
To put it another way, the justification condition was meant to ensure that
knowledge was based on solid evidence rather than on luck or misinformation,
but Gettier-type examples seem to show that justified true belief can still
involve luck and thus fall short of knowledge. This problem is referred to as
“the Gettier problem.” To solve this problem, we must either show that all
instances of justified true belief do indeed constitute knowledge, or
alternatively refine our analysis of knowledge.
EMPIRICISM
Empiricism is the theory that experience is of primary importance in
giving us knowledge of the world. Whatever we learn, according to empiricists,
we learn through perception. Knowledge without experience, with the possible
exception of trivial semantic and logical truths, is impossible.
Empiricism is the philosophical concept that experience, which is
based on observation and experimentation, is the source of knowledge. According
to empiricism, only the information that a person gathers with his or her
senses should be used to make decisions, without regard to reason or to either
religious or political teachings.
Primarily,
and in its psychology application, the term signifies the theory that the
phenomena of consciousness are simply the product of sensuous experience, i.e.
of sensations variously associated and arranged. It is thus distinguished from
Nativism or Innatism. Secondarily, and in its logical (epistemological) usage,
it designates the theory that all human knowledge is derived exclusively from
experience, the latter term meaning, either explicitly or implicitly, external
sense-percepts and internal representations and inferences exclusive of any
superorganic (immaterial) intellectual factor. In this connection it is opposed
to Intellectualism, Rationalism, and Apriorism. The two usages evidently
designate but two inseparable aspects of one and the same theory the
epistemological being the application of the psychological to the problem of
knowledge.
EMPIRICISM THEORIES
Classical Empiricism
Classical empiricism is characterized by a rejection of innate,
in-born knowledge or concepts. John Locke, well known as an empiricist, wrote
of the mind being a tabula rasa, a “blank slate”, when we enter the world. At
birth we know nothing; it is only subsequently that the mind is furnished with
information by experience.
Radical Empiricism
In its most radical forms, empiricism holds that all of our knowledge
is derived from the senses. This position leads naturally to the
verificationist principle that the meaning of statements is inextricably tied
to the experiences that would confirm them. According to this principle, it is
only if it is possible to empirically test a claim that the claim has meaning.
As all of our information comes from our senses, it is impossible for us to
talk about that which we have not experienced. Statements that are not tied to
our experiences are therefore meaningless.
This principle, which was associated with a now unpopular position
called logical positivism, renders religious and ethical claims literally
nonsensical. No observations could confirm religious or ethical claims,
therefore those claims are meaningless. Radical empiricism thus requires the
abandonment of religious and ethical discourse, let alone belief.
Moderate Empiricism
More moderate empiricists, however, allow that there may be some
cases in which the senses do not ground our knowledge, but hold that these are
exceptions to a general rule. Truths such as “there are no four-sided
triangles” and “7+5=12” need not be investigated in order to be known, but all
significant, interesting knowledge, the empiricist claims, comes to us from
experience. This more moderate empiricism strikes many as more plausible than
its radical alternative.
EMPIRICISM PRINCIPAL FORMS
Empiricism
appears in the history of philosophy three principal forms: (1) Materialism,
(2) Sensism, and (3) Positivism.
Materialism
Materialism in its crudest shape was taught by the ancient atomist (Democritus, Leucippus, Epicurus,
Lucretius), who, reducing the sum of all reality to atoms and motion, taught
that experience, whereof they held knowledge to be constituted, is generated by
images reflected from material objects through the sensory organs into the
soul. The soul, a mere complexus of the finest atoms, perceives not the objects
but their effluent images. With modern materialists (Helvetius, d'Holbach,
Diderot, Feuerbach, Moleschott, Büchner, Vogt, etc.), knowledge is accounted
for either by cerebral secretion or by motion; while Häcket looks on it as a
physiological process effected by certain brain cells. Avenarius, Willy, Mach,
etc. subtilize this process so far as to reduce all experience to internal
(empirio-criticism).
Sensism
All
materialists are of course sensists. Though the converse is not the case,
nevertheless, by denying any essential difference between sensations andideas
(intellectual states), sensism logically involves materialism. Sensism, which
is found with Empedocles and Protagoras amongst the ancients, was given its
first systematic form by Locke (d. 1704), though Bacon (d. 1626) and Hobbes (d.
1679) had prepared the data.
Locke
derives all simple ideas from external experience (sensations), all compound
ideas (modes, substances, relations) from internal experience (reflection).
Substance and cause are simply associations of subjective phenomena; universal
ideas are mere mental figments. Locke admits the existence, though he denies
the demonstrability, in man of an immaterial and immortal principle, the soul.
Berkeley (d.
1753), accepting the teaching of Locke that ideas are only transfigured
sensations, subjectivizes not only the sensible or secondary qualities of
matter (sensibilia propria,
e.g. colour and sound) as his predecessor had done, but also the primary
qualities (sensibilia communia,
extension, space, etc.), which Locke held to be objective. Berkeley denies the
objective basis of universal ideas and indeed of the whole material universe.
The reality of things he places in their being perceived (esse rei est percipi), and this
"perceivedness" is effected in the mind by God, not by the object or
subject. He still retains the substance-reality of the human soul and of
spirits generally, God included.
Hume (d.
1776) agrees with his two empiricist predecessors in teaching that the mind
knows only its own subjective organic impressions, whereof ideas are but the
images. The supersensible is therefore unknowable; the principle of causality
is resolved into a mere feeling of successiveness of phenomena; its necessity
is reduced to a subjective feeling resulting from uniform association
experienced in consciousness, and the spiritual essence or substantial being of
the soul is dissipated into a series of conscious states. Locke's sensism was
taken up by Condillac (d. 1780), who eliminated entirely the subjective factor
(Locke's "reflection") and sought to explain all cognitional states
by a mere mechanical, passive transformation of external sensations. The French
sensist retained the spiritual soul, but his followers disposed of it as Hume
had done with the Berkeleian soul relic. The Herbartians confound the image
with the idea, nor does Wundt make a clear distinction between primitive
concepts (empirische Begriffe,
representations of individual objects) and the image: "Denken ist
Phantasieren in Begriffen und Phantasieren ist Denken in Bildern".
Positivism
Positivists,
following Comte (d. 1857), do not deny the supersensible; they declare it
unknowable; the one source of cognition, they claim, is sense-experience,
experiment, and induction from phenomena. John Stuart Mill (d. 1870), following
Hume, reduces all knowledge to series of conscious states linked by empirical
associations and enlarged by inductive processes. The mind has no certitude of
an external world, but only of "a permanent possibility of
sensations" and antecedent and anticipated feelings. Spencer (d. 1903)
makes all knowledge relative. The actual existence of things is their
persistence in consciousness. Consciousness contains only subjective feelings.
The relative supposes the absolute, but the latter is unknowable to us; it is
the object of faith and religion (Agnoticism). All things, mind included, have
resulted from a cosmical process of mechanical evolution wherein they are still
involved; hence all concepts and principles are in a continuous flux.
KEY PROPONENTS
John Locke
Locke’s empiricism emphasizes the importance
of the experience of the senses in pursuit of knowledge rather than intuitive
speculation or deduction. The empiricist doctrine was first expounded by
English philosopher and statesman Francis Bacon early in the 17th century, but
Locke gave it systematic expression in his Essay Concerning Human
Understanding (1690). He regarded the mind of a person at birth as a tabula
rasa, a blank slate upon which experience imprinted knowledge, and did not
believe in intuition or theories of innate conceptions. Locke also held that
all persons are born good, independent, and equal.
Immanuel Kant
Kant argues that the blank
slate model of the mind is insufficient to explain the beliefs about objects
that we have; some components of our beliefs must be brought by the mind to
experience.
Kant expresses deep
dissatisfaction with the idealistic and seemingly skeptical results of the
empirical lines of inquiry. In each case, Kant gives a number of arguments to
show that Locke’s, Berkeley’s, and Hume’s empiricist positions are untenable
because they necessarily presupposes the very claims they set out to disprove.
In fact, any coherent account of how we perform even the most rudimentary
mental acts of self-awareness and making judgments about objects must
presuppose these claims, Kant argues. Hence, while Kant is sympathetic with
many parts of empiricism, ultimately it cannot be a satisfactory account of our
experience of the world.
George Berkeley
Berkeley’s strict
phenomenalism, in contrast to Locke, raised questions about the inference from
the character of our sensations to conclusions about the real properties of
mind-independent objects. Since the human mind is strictly limited to the
senses for its input, Berkeley argued, it has no independent means by which to
verify the accuracy of the match between sensations and the properties that
objects possess in themselves. In fact, Berkeley rejected the very idea of
mind-independent objects on the grounds that a mind is, by its nature,
incapable of possessing an idea of such a thing. Hence, in Kant’s terms,
Berkeley was a material idealist. To the material idealist, knowledge of
material objects is ideal or unachievable, not real. For Berkeley,
mind-independent material objects are impossible and unknowable. In our sense
experience we only have access to our mental representations, not to objects
themselves. Berkeley argues that our judgments about objects are really
judgments about these mental representations alone, not the substance that
gives rise to them. In the Refutation
of Material Idealism, Kant argues that material idealism is
actually incompatible with a position that Berkeley held, namely that we are
capable of making judgments about our experience.
David Hume
David Hume pursued Berkeley’s
empirical line of inquiry even further, calling into question even more of our
common sense beliefs about the source and support of our sense perceptions.
Hume maintains that we cannot provide a priori or a posteriori justifications
for a number of our beliefs like, “Objects and subjects persist identically over
time,” or “Every event must have a cause.” In Hume’s hands, it becomes clear
that empiricism cannot give us an epistemological justification for the claims
about objects, subjects, and causes that we took to be most obvious and certain
about the world.
RATIONALISM
The Latin word ratio meaning reason.
Rationalism (from Lat. rationalis, pertaining to reason, ratio), a term
employed both in philosophy and in theology for any system which sets up human
reason as the final criterion and chief source of knowledge. Such systems are
opposed to all doctrines which rest solely or ultimately upon external
authority; the individual must investigate everything for himself and abandon
any position the validity of which cannot be rationally demonstrated.
Philosophical rationalism is that theory of knowledge which maintains
that reason is in and by itself a source of knowledge, and that knowledge so
derived has superior authority over knowledge acquired through sensation. This
view is opposed to the various systems which regard the mind as a tabula rasa
(blank tablet) in which the outside world as it were imprints itself through
the senses. The opposition between rationalism and sensationalism is, however,
rarely so simple and direct, inasmuch as many thinkers (e.g. Locke) have
admitted both sensation and reflection. Such philosophies are called
rationalist or sensationalist according as they lay emphasis specially on the
function of reason or that of the senses.
More generally, philosophic rationalism is opposed
to empirical theories of knowledge, inasmuch as it regards all true knowledge
as deriving deductively from fundamental elementary concepts.
RATIONALISM THEORIES
1) The
Intuition/Deduction Thesis
The Intuition/Deduction thesis concerns how we become warranted in
believing propositions in a particular subject area.The Intuition/Deduction
Thesis: Some propositions in a particular subject area, S, are knowable by us
by intuition alone; still others are knowable by being deduced from intuited
propositions.Intuition is a form of rational insight. Intellectually grasping a
proposition, we just "see" it to be true in such a way as to form a
true, warranted belief in it. Deduction is a process in which we derive
conclusions from intuited premises through valid arguments, ones in which the
conclusion must be true if the premises are true. We intuit, for example, that
the number three is prime and that it is greater than two. We then deduce from
this knowledge that there is a prime number greater than two. Intuition and
deduction thus provide us with knowledge a priori, which is to say knowledge
gained independently of sense experience.
We can generate different versions of the Intuition/Deduction thesis
by substituting different subject areas for the variable ‘S’. Some rationalists
take mathematics to be knowable by intuition and deduction. Some place ethical
truths in this category. Some include metaphysical claims, such as that God
exists, we have free will, and our mind and body are distinct substances. The
more propositions rationalists include within the range of intuition and
deduction, and the more controversial the truth of those propositions, the more
radical their rationalism.
Rationalists also vary the strength of their view by adjusting their
understanding of warrant. Some take warranted beliefs to be beyond even the
slightest doubt and claim that intuition and deduction provide beliefs of this
high epistemic status. Others interpret warrant more conservatively, say as
belief beyond a reasonable doubt, and claim that intuition and deduction
provide beliefs of that caliber. Still another dimension of rationalism depends
on how its proponents understand the connection between intuition, on the one
hand, and truth, on the other. Some take intuition to be infallible, claiming
that whatever we intuit must be true. Others allow for the possibility of false
intuited propositions.
2) The Innate Knowledge
Thesis
We have knowledge of some truths in a particular subject area, S, as
part of our rational nature. Like the Intuition/Deduction thesis, the Innate
Knowledge thesis asserts the existence of knowledge gained a priori,
independently of experience. The difference between them rests in the
accompanying understanding of how this a priori knowledge is gained. The
Intuition/Deduction thesis cites intuition and subsequent deductive reasoning.
The Innate Knowledge thesis offers our rational nature. Our innate knowledge is
not learned through either sense experience or intuition and deduction. It is
just part of our nature. Experiences may trigger a process by which we bring
this knowledge to consciousness, but the experiences do not provide us with the
knowledge itself. It has in some way been with us all along. According to some
rationalists, we gained the knowledge in an earlier existence. According to
others, God provided us with it at creation. Still others say it is part of our
nature through natural selection.
We get different versions of the Innate Knowledge thesis by
substituting different subject areas for the variable ‘S'. Once again, the more
subjects included within the range of the thesis or the more controversial the
claim to have knowledge in them, the more radical the form of rationalism.
Stronger and weaker understandings of warrant yield stronger and weaker
versions of the thesis as well.
3) The Innate Concept
Thesis:
We have some of the concepts we employ in a particular subject area,
S, as part of our rational nature. According to the Innate Concept thesis, some
of our concepts are not gained from experience. They are part of our rational
nature in such a way that, while sense experiences may trigger a process by
which they are brought to consciousness, experience does not provide the
concepts or determine the information they contain. Some claim that the Innate
Concept thesis is entailed by the Innate Knowledge Thesis; a particular
instance of knowledge can only be innate if the concepts that are contained in
the known proposition are also innate. This is Locke's position. Others, such
as Carruthers, argue against this connection.
The content and strength of the Innate Concept thesis varies with the
concepts claimed to be innate. The more a concept seems removed from experience
and the mental operations we can perform on what experience provides the more
plausibly it may be claimed to be innate. Since we do not experience perfect
triangles but do experience pains, our concept of the former is a more
promising candidate than our concept of the latter for being innate.
KEY PROPONENTS
RENÉ DESCARTES
1. Descartes is a
rationalist who set out to refute radical skepticism on its
own turf.
own turf.
He
sought an absolute foundation for knowledge by proposing to doubt
all things and accept as knowledge (or at least as a foundation for
knowledge) only what could not be doubted. (Note that this requirement
of absolute certainty [undoubtability] was not Plato's or Aristotle's
criterion for knowledge.)
all things and accept as knowledge (or at least as a foundation for
knowledge) only what could not be doubted. (Note that this requirement
of absolute certainty [undoubtability] was not Plato's or Aristotle's
criterion for knowledge.)
2.
Descartes' procedure is to withhold his belief from anything that is not
entirely certain and indubitable.
entirely certain and indubitable.
This leads him to consider the possibility that instead of a benevolent God,
there is a powerful and evil demon systematically deceiving him into
thinking things to be so that are not in fact so. This leads him to conclude
as doubtable, and therefore as not knowledge,
sense experience, and all that sense experience testifies to (e.g., that
there is an external world, other people, and even that he has a
body),
his conviction that what he takes to be waking reality is real and not a
dream (or a cosmic deception),
his memory, and
intellectual calculation (e.g., 2 + 3 = 5).
there is a powerful and evil demon systematically deceiving him into
thinking things to be so that are not in fact so. This leads him to conclude
as doubtable, and therefore as not knowledge,
sense experience, and all that sense experience testifies to (e.g., that
there is an external world, other people, and even that he has a
body),
his conviction that what he takes to be waking reality is real and not a
dream (or a cosmic deception),
his memory, and
intellectual calculation (e.g., 2 + 3 = 5).
3.
The one thing Descartes finds to be absolutely certain in the midst of
radical doubt and possible deception is that thinking (especially in the
mode of doubt) exists, that he as a thinking thing exists.
radical doubt and possible deception is that thinking (especially in the
mode of doubt) exists, that he as a thinking thing exists.
This will become Descartes' foundational truth
and the measure of all other truth: Cogito [I think], ergo [therefore]
sum [I am].
4. From there Descartes investigates, solely on the basis of dialectical
reasoning apart from reliance upon what has proved to be doubtable,
and concludes
reasoning apart from reliance upon what has proved to be doubtable,
and concludes
a. What must be the criterion of knowledge -- namely, a candidate for
belief whose certainty is wholly evident to the reflecting mind with
the "clarity and distinctness" of the cogito's existence to itself;
b. What his essential nature must be -- namely, a thing that thinks
(including also doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wills, refuses,
imagines, and feels); and
c. What, to the contrary, must be the essential nature of the bodies to
which our senses uncertainly testify -- namely, things which are
extended in space.
belief whose certainty is wholly evident to the reflecting mind with
the "clarity and distinctness" of the cogito's existence to itself;
b. What his essential nature must be -- namely, a thing that thinks
(including also doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wills, refuses,
imagines, and feels); and
c. What, to the contrary, must be the essential nature of the bodies to
which our senses uncertainly testify -- namely, things which are
extended in space.
5. Descartes goes on to extend his foundation for knowledge and show
how it can provide a basis for the general trustworthiness of sense
perception, memory, and intellectual calculation, among other things,
by offering what he believes to be proof of the existence and goodness
of an infinitely powerful, wise, and good creator of himself (as a finite
and fallible mind), a creator whose goodness would never allow his
creature to be comprehensively deceived.
how it can provide a basis for the general trustworthiness of sense
perception, memory, and intellectual calculation, among other things,
by offering what he believes to be proof of the existence and goodness
of an infinitely powerful, wise, and good creator of himself (as a finite
and fallible mind), a creator whose goodness would never allow his
creature to be comprehensively deceived.
6. Thus Descartes
believes he has provided a foundation, on the one
hand, for knowledge in morality and religion (in the mind's or soul's
givenness to itself) and, on the other hand, for knowledge in the natural
sciences (in the nature of physical bodies to which the senses give us
access).
hand, for knowledge in morality and religion (in the mind's or soul's
givenness to itself) and, on the other hand, for knowledge in the natural
sciences (in the nature of physical bodies to which the senses give us
access).
IMMANUEL KANT
Kant’s Refutation of Material Idealism works against Descartes’
project as well as Berkeley’s. Descartes believed that he could infer the
existence of objects in space outside of him based on his awareness of his own
existence coupled with an argument that God exists and is not deceiving him
about the evidence of his senses. Kant argues in the Refutation chapter that
knowledge of external objects cannot be inferential. Rather, the capacity to be
aware of one’s own existence in Descartes’ famous cogito argument already
presupposes that existence of objects in space and time outside of me.
Kant had also come to doubt the claims of the Rationalists because of
what he called Antinomies, or contradictory, but validly proven pairs of claims
that reason is compelled toward. From the basic principles that the
Rationalists held, it is possible, Kant argues, to prove conflicting claims
like, “The world has a beginning in time and is limited as regards space,” and
“The world has no beginning and no limits in space.” (A 426/B 454) Kant claims
that antinomies like this one reveal fundamental methodological and
metaphysical mistakes in the rationalist project. The contradictory claims
could both be proven because they both shared the mistaken metaphysical
assumption that we can have knowledge of things as they are in themselves,
independent of the conditions of our experience of them.
The Antinomies can be resolved, Kant argues, if we understand the
proper function and domain of the various faculties that contribute to produce
knowledge. We must recognize that we cannot know things as they are in
themselves and that our knowledge is subject to the conditions of our
experience. The Rationalist project was doomed to failure because it did not
take note of the contribution that our faculty of reason makes to our
experience of objects. Their a priori analysis of our ideas could inform us
about the content of our ideas, but it could not give a coherent demonstration
of metaphysical truths about the external world, the self, the soul, God, and
so on.
PLATO
Plato was a major rationalist. He rejected all sense experience. For
him, the problem of the one and the many meant that empiricism was useless.
“No man ever steps in the same river twice, for it's not the same
river and he's not the same man.” 5
Yep, that is the problem of the one and the many by Heraclitus,
quoted by Plato in Cratylus. As mentioned previously, the world is in a state
of flux, so knowledge from a state of flux leads to knowledge that is itself
flawed.
Instead, Plato deduced that we ‘recollected’ knowledge from
ex-temporal (outside of time) abstract entities called forms. Each object or
concept in this world has a correlating form in the, aptly named, realm of the
forms. The forms are immune to the constrains of this world, like decay, so
they are perfect in every way.
REFERENCES
Comments
Post a Comment